1.2 eng
All checks were successful
continuous-integration/drone/push Build is passing

This commit is contained in:
Simple_Not 2023-07-19 21:23:52 +10:00
parent 34b71ccb10
commit 110eb5bb75
2 changed files with 53 additions and 37 deletions

View File

@ -0,0 +1,40 @@
### 1.2 The instrumentalization of the scientific image
----
> перевeди это
It should come as no surprise then that the manifest image continues to provide the fundamental framework within which much contempo- rary philosophizing is carried out. It encompasses not only the major schools of contemporary Continental thought by which Sellars, writing at the beginning of the 1960s, presumably meant phe- nomenology and existentialism, to which we should add critical theory, hermeneutics, and post-structuralism but also the trends of contem- porary British and American philosophy which emphasize the analysis of “common sense” and “ordinary usage” […] For all these philosophies can be fruitfully construed as more or less adequate accounts of the manifest image of man-in-the-world, which accounts are then taken to be an adequate and full description in general terms of what man and the world really are (Sellars 1963a: 8). Despite their otherwise intractable differences, what all these philosophies share is a more or less profound hostility to the idea that the scientific image describes what there really is, that it has an ontological purchase capable of undermining mans manifest self-conception as a person or intentional agent. Ultimately, all the philosophies carried out under the aegis of the manifest image whether they acknowledge its existence or not are united by the common conviction that all the postulated entities of the scientific image [e.g., elementary particles, neurophysiological mechanisms, evolutionary processes, etc.] are symbolic tools which func- tion (something like the distance-measuring devices which are rolled around on maps) to help us find our way around in the world, but do not themselves describe actual objects or processes (Sellars 1963a: 32). This instrumentalist conception of science is the inevitable corollary of any philosophy that insists on the irrecusable primacy of mans manifest self-understanding. Thus, although they are the totems of two otherwise divergent philosophical traditions, the two canonical twentieth-century philosophers, Heidegger and Wittgenstein, share the conviction that the manifest image enjoys a philosophical privilege vis-à-vis the scientific image, and that the sorts of entities and processes postulated by scientific theory are in some way founded upon, or deriva- tive of, our more originary, pre-scientific understanding, whether this be construed in terms of our being-in-the-world, or our practical engage- ment in language-games. From there, one may or may not decide to take the short additional step which consists in denouncing the scientific image as a cancerous excrescence of the manifest image (this is a theme to which we shall have occasion to return in chapters 2 and 3).
----
> перевeди это
To his considerable credit, Sellars adamantly refused this instru- mentalization of the scientific image. For as he pointed out, the fact that the manifest image enjoys a methodological primacy as the originary framework from which the scientific image developed in no way legiti- mates attempts to ascribe a substantive primacy to it. In other words, even if the scientific image remains methodologically dependent upon the manifest image, this in no way undermines its substantive auton- omy vis-à-vis the latter. In this regard, it should be pointed out (although Sellars does not do so) that to construe scientific theory as an efflorescence from the more fundamental phenomenological and/or pragmatic substratum of our manifest being-in-the-world is to endorse a form of philosophical reductionism with regard to science. Yet unlike its oft-criticized scientific counterpart, the tenets of which are fairly explicit, even when it cannot carry out in fact the reductions it claims to be able to perform in principle, partisans of this philosophical reduc- tionism about science conspicuously avoid delineating the conceptual criteria in accordance with which the structures of the scientific image might be reduced to the workings of the manifest image. Unsurprisingly, those who would instrumentalize the scientific image prefer to remain silent about the chasm that separates the trivial assertion that scientific theorizing supervenes on pre-scientific practice, from the far-from-trivial demonstration which would explain precisely how, for example, quantum mechanics is a function of our ability to wield hammers.
----
> перевeди это
Sellars never succumbed to the lure of this crass philosophical reduc- tionism with regard to the scientific image, insisting that philosophy should resist attempts to subsume the scientific image within the manifest image. At the same time, Sellars enjoined philosophers to abstain from the opposite temptation, which would consist in trying to supplant the manifest image with the scientific one. For Sellars, this cannot be an option, since it would entail depriving ourselves of what makes us human. However, it is important to note that the very terms in which Sellars formulated his hoped for synthesis between the mani- fest and scientific images continue to assume the incorrigibility of the characterization of rational purposiveness concomitant with the Jonesean theory of agency. Yet it is precisely this model of rational- purposive agency along with the accompanying recommendation that the scientific image should be tethered to purposes commensurate with the workings of the manifest image which some contemporary philosophers who refuse to sideline the scientific image are calling into question. These philosophers propose instead obviously disregarding the Sellarsian edict that the manifest image be integrated into the scientific image. While for Sellars it was precisely the manifest images theoretical status which ensured its normative autonomy, and hence its ineliminability as an account of the nature of rational agency, for Paul Churchland, an ex-student of Sellars who has explicitly acknowl- edged the latters influence,4 the manifest image is revisable precisely because it is a corrigible speculative achievement that cannot be accepted as the definitive account of rational purposiveness. Indeed, for Churchland, there is no guarantee that the latter notion indexes anything real independently of the particular theoretical framework embodied in the manifest image. Though the manifest image undeni- ably marked a significant cognitive achievement in the cultural devel- opment of humankind, it can no longer remain insulated from critical scrutiny. And while the adoption of the propositional attitude idiom in subjective reports seems to have endowed the manifest image with a quasi-sacrosanct status, lending it an aura of incorrigible authenticity, this merely obscures its inherently speculative status. Thus, Churchland invites us to envisage the following possibility:
----
> перевeди это
> [A] spontaneous introspective judgement is just an instance of an acquired habit of conceptual response to ones internal states, and the integrity of any particular response is always contingent on the integrity of the acquired conceptual framework (theory) in which the response is framed. Accordingly, ones own introspective certainty that ones mind is the seat of beliefs and desires [or purposes] may be as badly misplaced as was the classical mans visual certainty that the star-flecked sphere of the heavens turns daily.
>
> (P. M. Churchland 1989: 3)
----
> перевeди это
Where Sellars believed stereoscopic integration of the two images could be achieved by wedding the mechanistic discourse of causation to the rational language of intention, Churchland proposes to supplant the latter altogether via a neurocomputational enhancement of the scientific image which would effectively allow it to annex the manifest image, thereby forcing us to revise our understanding of ourselves as autonomous rational agents or persons. However, as we shall see below, Churchlands attempt to annex the manifest image to the scientific image is vitiated by a fundamental epistemological tension. Like Sellars, Churchland emphatically rejects the instrumentalist conception of science concomitant with the ontological prioritization of the manifest image: he claims to be a scientific realist. But as we shall see, his realism about sci- ence is mined at every turn by his pragmatist construal of representation.
----

View File

@ -1,43 +1,19 @@
stringo = """ stringo = """
Accordingly, for Sellars, the fundamental import of the manifest Where Sellars believed stereoscopic integration of the two images
image is not so much ontological as normative, in the sense that it could be achieved by wedding the mechanistic discourse of causation to
provides the framework in which we think of one another as sharing the rational language of intention, Churchland proposes to supplant the
the community intentions which provides the ambience of principles latter altogether via a neurocomputational enhancement of the scientific
and standards (above all those which make meaningful discourse and image which would effectively allow it to annex the manifest image,
rationality itself possible) within which we live our own individual thereby forcing us to revise our understanding of ourselves as autonomous
lives(Sellars 1963a: 40). Thus, the manifest image does not so much rational agents or persons. However, as we shall see below, Churchlands
catalogue a set of indispensable ontological items which we should attempt to annex the manifest image to the scientific image is vitiated
strive to preserve from scientific reduction; rather, it indexes the com- by a fundamental epistemological tension. Like Sellars, Churchland
munity of rational agents. In this regard, the primary component of the emphatically rejects the instrumentalist conception of science con-
manifest image, Sellars suggests, is the notion of persons as loci of comitant with the ontological prioritization of the manifest image: he
intentional agency. Consequently, although the manifest image is a claims to be a scientific realist. But as we shall see, his realism about sci-
disciplined and critical theoretical framework, one which could also be ence is mined at every turn by his pragmatist construal of representation.
said to constitute a certain kind of scientific image albeit one that is
correlational as opposed to postulational (Sellars 1963a: 7) it is not
one which we are in a position simply to take or leave. For unlike
other theoretical frameworks, Sellars maintains, the manifest image
provides the ineluctable prerequisite for our capacity to identify our-
selves as human, which is to say, as persons: [M]an is that being which
conceives of itself in terms of the manifest image. To the extent that
the manifest image does not survive [] to that extent man himself
would not survive (Sellars 1963a: 18). What is indispensable about our
manifest self-image, Sellars concludes, is not its ontological commit-
ments, in the sense of what it says exists in the world, but rather its
normative valence as the framework which allows us to make sense of
ourselves as rational agents engaged in pursuing various purposes in
the world. Without it, we would simply not know what to do or how to
make sense of ourselves indeed, we would no longer be able to recog-
nize ourselves as human. Accordingly, Sellars, echoing Kant, concludes
that we have no option but to insist that the manifest image enjoys a
practical, if not theoretical, priority over the scientific image, since it
provides the source for the norm of rational purposiveness, which we
cannot do without. In this regard, the genuine philosophical task,
according to Sellars, would consist in achieving a properly stereoscopic
integration of the manifest and scientific images, such that the language
of rational intention would come to enrich scientific theory so as to
allow the latter to be directly wedded to human purposes.
""" """
print( print(